Results for 'Darlene S. Richardson'

944 found
Order:
  1.  12
    Women in Science: 5000 Years of Obstacles and Achievements.Darlene S. Richardson - 1992 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 12 (4-5):187-191.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  11
    Ordinary and Extraordinary Women in Science.Connie J. Sutton & Darlene S. Richardson - 1993 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 13 (5):251-254.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  35
    Modern Art and Scientific ThoughtThe Poem as Plant: A Biological View of Goethe's Faust.Horst S. Daemmrich, John Adkins Richardson & Peter Salm - 1972 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 30 (3):407.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  11
    Handbook for Achieving Gender Equity Through Education.Susan S. Klein, Barbara Richardson, Dolores A. Grayson, Lynn H. Fox, Cheris Kramarae, Diane S. Pollard & Carol Anne Dwyer (eds.) - 2007 - Routledge.
    First published in 1985, the _Handbook for Achieving Gender Equity Through Education_ quickly established itself as the essential reference work concerning gender equity in education. This new, expanded edition provides a 20-year retrospective of the field, one that has the great advantage of documenting U.S. national data on the gains and losses in the efforts to advance gender equality through policies such as Title IX, the landmark federal law prohibiting sex discrimination in education, equity programs and research. Key features include:_ (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  17
    The dual function of social gaze.Matthias S. Gobel, Heejung S. Kim & Daniel C. Richardson - 2015 - Cognition 136 (C):359-364.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  6.  20
    Effects of loss of sleep. II.E. S. Robinson & F. Richardson-Robinson - 1922 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 5 (2):93.
  7.  3
    Friedrich Stadler: The Vienna Circle: Studies in the Origins, Development and Influence of Logical Empiricism. [REVIEW]S. Steed & A. Richardson - 2003 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (1):169-172.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Institutionally Divided Moral Responsibility*: HENRY S. RICHARDSON.Henry S. Richardson - 1999 - Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (2):218-249.
    I am going to be discussing a mode of moral responsibility that anglophone philosophers have largely neglected. It is a type of responsibility that looks to the future rather than the past. Because this forward-looking moral responsibility is relatively unfamiliar in the lexicon of analytic philosophy, many of my locutions will initially strike many readers as odd. As a matter of everyday speech, however, the notion of forward-looking moral responsibility is perfectly familiar. Today, for instance, I said I would be (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  9.  17
    Philosophy for Children in Louisville.Frederick S. Oscanyan & Brenda C. Richardson - 1983 - Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children 4 (3-4):6-8.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  24
    Children’s Relationship With Their Pet Dogs and OXTR Genotype Predict Child–Pet Interaction in an Experimental Setting.Darlene A. Kertes, Nathan Hall & Samarth S. Bhatt - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  37
    Postgenomics: Perspectives on Biology after the Genome.Sarah S. Richardson & Hallam Stevens (eds.) - 2015 - Duke University Press.
    Ten years after the Human Genome Project’s completion the life sciences stand in a moment of uncertainty, transition, and contestation. The postgenomic era has seen rapid shifts in research methodology, funding, scientific labor, and disciplinary structures. Postgenomics is transforming our understanding of disease and health, our environment, and the categories of race, class, and gender. At the same time, the gene retains its centrality and power in biological and popular discourse. The contributors to Postgenomics analyze these ruptures and continuities and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  12.  24
    Articulating the Moral Community: Toward a Constructive Ethical Pragmatism.Henry S. Richardson - 2018 - New York, US: Oup Usa.
    Henry S. Richardson is Professor of Philosophy at Georgetown University. From 2008-18, he was the editor of Ethics. His previous books include Practical Reasoning about Final Ends, Democratic Autonomy, and Moral Entanglements. He has held fellowships sponsored by the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation, the National Endowment for the Humanities, and the University Center for Human Values at Princeton University.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  13. Practical Reasoning About Final Ends.Henry S. Richardson - 1994 - Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
    Henry Richardson argues that we can determine our ends rationally. He constructs a rich and original theory of how we can reason about our final goals. Richardson defuses the counter-arguments for the limits of rational deliberation, and develops interesting ideas about how his model might be extended to interpersonal deliberation of ends, taking him to the borders of political theory. Along the way Richardson offers illuminating discussions of, inter alia, Aristotle, Aquinas, Sidgwick, and Dewey, as well as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  14. Sexes, species, and genomes: why males and females are not like humans and chimpanzees.Sarah S. Richardson - 2010 - Biology and Philosophy 25 (5):823-841.
    This paper describes, analyzes, and critiques the construction of separate “male” and “female” genomes in current human genome research. Comparative genomic work on human sex differences conceives of the sexes as like different species, with different genomes. I argue that this construct is empirically unsound, distortive to research, and ethically questionable. I propose a conceptual model of biological sex that clarifies the distinction between species and sexes as genetic classes. The dynamic interdependence of the sexes makes them “dyadic kinds” that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15.  15
    Moral Entanglements: The Ancillary-Care Obligations of Medical Researchers.Henry S. Richardson - 2012 - Oup Usa.
    The philosopher Henry Richardson's short book is a defense of a position on a neglected topic in medical research ethics. Clinical research ethics has been a longstanding area of study, dating back to the aftermath of the Nazi death-camp doctors and the Tuskegee syphilis study. Most ethical regulations and institutions have developed in response to those past abuses, including the stress on obtaining informed consent from the subject. Richardson points out that that these ethical regulations do not address (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  16.  49
    Autonomy's Many Normative Presuppositions.Henry S. Richardson - 2001 - American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (3):287 - 303.
  17. Estlund’s Promising Account of Democratic Authority.Henry S. Richardson - 2011 - Ethics 121 (2):301-334.
    David Estlund’s Democratic Authority develops a novel doctrine of “normative consent,” according to which the nonconsent of those with a duty to consent is null. This article suggests that this doctrine can be defended by confining it to contexts involving consent to an authority, which raise distinctive normative challenges, but argues that Estlund’s attempt to deploy the doctrine fails, for it does not provide convincing reasons to think that citizens have any duty to consent. In closing, the article suggests that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18.  33
    Bioethics: A Return to Fundamentals.Henry S. Richardson, Bernard Gert, Charles M. Culver & K. Danner Clouser - 1999 - Hastings Center Report 29 (5):36.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  19.  21
    More-Than-Partial Entrustment in Pragmatic Clinical Trials.Henry S. Richardson - 2023 - American Journal of Bioethics 23 (8):42-45.
    Morain and Largent’s (2023) thorough and thoughtful article concludes that the partial-entrustment model of medical researchers’ ancillary-care obligations (Richardson and Belsky 2004; Belsky and R...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20. Moral Reasoning.Henry S. Richardson - 2013 - The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Moral reasoning is individual or collective practical reasoning about what, morally, one ought to do. Philosophical examination of moral reasoning faces both distinctive puzzles — about how we recognize moral considerations and cope with conflicts among them and about how they move us to act — and distinctive opportunities for gleaning insight about what we ought to do from how we reason about what we ought to do.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  21. (1 other version)Practical Reasoning about Final Ends.Henry S. Richardson - 1996 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 58 (4):782-783.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  22. Rawlsian social-contract theory and the severely disabled.Henry S. Richardson - 2006 - The Journal of Ethics 10 (4):419-462.
    Martha Nussbaum has powerfully argued in Frontiers ofJustice and elsewhere that John Rawls’s sort of social-contract theory cannot usefully be deployed to deal with issues pertaining to justice for the disabled. To counter this claim, this article deploys Rawls’s sort of social-contract theory in order to deal with issues pertaining to justice for the disabled—or, since, as Nussbaum stresses, we all have some degree of disability—for the severely disabled. In this way, rather than questioning one by one Nussbaum’s interpretive claims (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  23. Specifying norms as a way to resolve concrete ethical problems.Henry S. Richardson - 1990 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (4):279-310.
  24.  29
    Partial Entrustment in Pragmatic Clinical Trials.Henry S. Richardson & Mildred K. Cho - 2020 - American Journal of Bioethics 20 (1):24-26.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  23
    Commensurability as a Prerequisite of Rational Choice: An Examination of Sidgwick's Position.Henry S. Richardson - 1991 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 8 (2):181 - 197.
  26.  14
    (1 other version)Desire and the Good in De Anima.Henry S. Richardson - 1992 - In Martha C. Nussbaum & Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's de Anima. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    This essay presents an interpretation of the theory of animal movement that emphasizes the place Aristotle accords the good as the object of desire and the coordinate importance he assigns to desire and discernment. This interpretation is based on two competing models: the desire-based model, where the shape of the account of any action is based on some one occurrent desire; and the good-based model, where the account starts from some object aimed at as good. It is argued that the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  47
    Announcing an Improvement to the Journal’s Blind Review Process.Henry S. Richardson - 2017 - Ethics 127 (3):519-520.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  96
    Moral Entanglements: Ad Hoc Intimacies and Ancillary Duties of Care.Henry S. Richardson - 2012 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 9 (3):376-409.
    This paper develops and explores the idea of moral entanglements: the ways in which, through innocent transactions with others, we can unintendedly accrue special obligations to them. More particularly, the paper explains intimacy-based moral entanglements, to which we become liable by accepting another's waiver of privacy rights. Sometimes, having entered into others' private affairs for innocent or even helpful reasons, one discovers needs of theirs that then become the focus of special duties of care. The general duty to warn them (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  29. Satisficing: Not good enough.Henry S. Richardson - 2004 - In Michael Byron (ed.), Satisficing and Maximizing: Moral Theorists on Practical Reason. New York, USA: Cambridge University Press. pp. 106--130.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  30.  57
    The Ancillary‐Care Responsibilities of Medical Researchers: An Ethical Framework for Thinking about the Clinical Care that Researchers Owe Their Subjects.Henry S. Richardson & Leah Belsky - 2004 - Hastings Center Report 34 (1):25-33.
    Researchers do not owe their subjects the same level of care that physicians owe patients, but they owe more than merely what the research protocol stipulates. In keeping with the dynamics of the relationship between researcher and subject, they have limited but substantive fiduciary obligations.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  31. Specifying, balancing, and interpreting bioethical principles.Henry S. Richardson - 2000 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (3):285 – 307.
    The notion that it is useful to specify norms progressively in order to resolve doubts about what to do, which I developed initially in a 1990 article, has been only partly assimilated by the bioethics literature. The thought is not just that it is helpful to work with relatively specific norms. It is more than that: specification can replace deductive subsumption and balancing. Here I argue against two versions of reliance on balancing that are prominent in recent bioethical discussions. Without (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  32. The Left Vienna Circle, Part 1. Carnap, Neurath, and the Left Vienna Circle thesis.Sarah S. Richardson - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (1):14-24.
    Recent scholarship resuscitates the history and philosophy of a ‘left wing’ in the Vienna Circle, offering a counterhistory to the conventional image of analytic philosophy as politically conformist. This paper disputes the historical claim that early logical empiricists developed a political philosophy of science. Though some individuals in the Vienna Circle, including Rudolf Carnap and Otto Neurath, believed strongly in the importance of science to social progress, they did not construct a political philosophy of science. Both Carnap and Neurath were (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  33.  47
    (1 other version)Truth and Ends in Dewey's Pragmatism.Henry S. Richardson - 1998 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28 (sup1):109-147.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  14
    12 Approaching Postgenomics.Sarah S. Richardson & Hallam Stevens - 2015 - In Sarah S. Richardson & Hallam Stevens (eds.), Postgenomics: Perspectives on Biology after the Genome. Duke University Press. pp. 232-242.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  5
    Commentary on Broadie.Henry S. Richardson - 1987 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 3 (1):253-261.
  36.  39
    Editorial: Quality and the Review Process.Henry S. Richardson - 2015 - Ethics 126 (1):1-6.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Gilles Deleuze's Time Machine.Darlene Pursley & D. N. Rodowick - 2000 - Substance 29 (1):159.
  38. The Left Vienna Circle, Part 2. The Left Vienna Circle, disciplinary history, and feminist philosophy of science.Sarah S. Richardson - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (2):167-174.
    This paper analyzes the claim that the Left Vienna Circle offers a theoretical and historical precedent for a politically engaged philosophy of science today. I describe the model for a political philosophy of science advanced by LVC historians. They offer this model as a moderate, properly philosophical approach to political philosophy of science that is rooted in the analytic tradition. This disciplinary-historical framing leads to weaknesses in LVC scholars’ conception of the history of the LVC and its contemporary relevance. In (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  39. Republicanism and democratic injustice.Henry S. Richardson - 2006 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 5 (2):175-200.
    A Theory of Freedom and Government has provided a systematic basis for republican theory in the idea of freedom as non-domination. Can a pure republican view, which confines itself to the normative resources thus afforded, adequately address the full range of issues of social justice? This article argues that while there are many sorts of structural injustice with which a pure republican view can well cope, unfair disparities in political influence, of the kind that Rawls labeled failures of the ‘fair (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  40.  94
    Degrees of finality and the highest good in Aristotle.Henry S. Richardson - 1992 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 30 (3):327-352.
    This article develops a uniform interpretation of "pursuit for the sake of an end", explaining what an "unqualified final" end (sought solely for its own sake) offers that a (merely) final one does not and providing an improved account of what Aristotle means by an "ultimate end". This interpretation sheds light on (1) the regress argument at the outset of "N.E." I.2, (2) the way Aristotle argues for the existence of a highest good, (3) the special contribution of "self-sufficiency" (autarkeia) (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  41. Liberalism, Deliberative Democracy, and “Reasons that All Can Accept”.Henry S. Richardson & James Bohman - 2009 - Journal of Political Philosophy 17 (3):253-274.
  42.  45
    Measurement, pleasure, and practical science in Plato's Protagoras.Henry S. Richardson - 1990 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 28 (1):7-32.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Measurement, Pleasure, and Practical Science in Plato's Protagoras HENRY S. RICHARDSON 1. INTRODUCTION TOWARDS THE END OF THE PROTAGORAS Socrates suggests that the "salvation of our life" depends upon applying to pleasures and pains a science of measurement (metr$tik~techn~).Whether Plato intended to portray Socrates as putting forward sincerely the form of hedonism that makes these pleasures and pains relevant has been the subject of a detailed and probably (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  29
    From the Archives: William Richardson’s Questions for Martin Heidegger’s “Preface”.William J. Richardson, Richard Capobianco & Ian Alexander Moore - 2019 - Gatherings: The Heidegger Circle Annual 9:1-27.
    Martin Heidegger wrote one and only one preface for a scholarly work on his thinking, and it was for William J. Richardson’s study Heidegger: Through Phenomenology to Thought, first published in 1963. Ever since, both Heidegger’s Preface and Richardson’s groundbreaking book have played an important role in Heidegger scholarship. Much has been discussed about these texts over the decades, but what has not been available to students and scholars up to this point is Richardson’s original comments and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Misreading of bioethics, root and branch-Reply.H. S. Richardson - 2000 - Hastings Center Report 30 (2):4-5.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  14
    Moral Psychology and Community.Henry S. Richardson & Paul J. Weithman (eds.) - 1999 - Taylor & Francis.
    First published in 2000. Routledge is an imprint of Taylor & Francis, an informa company.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  19
    Heidegger and Aristotle.William J. Richardson, S. J. - 1964 - Heythrop Journal 5 (1):58–64.
  47. The Logical Structure of Sittlichkeit.Henry S. Richardson - 1989 - Idealistic Studies 19 (1):62-78.
    Sittlichkeit seduces: Hegel’s third category of Right, intended to synthesize impartially derived rights with a subjectively centered morality of the good, understandably piques the hopes of his modern readers. How could it not? Sittlichkeit, Ethical Life, holds out the prospect of so much that we still seek. It promises to reconcile welfare and autonomy while guaranteeing concrete content for their product. By combining legal duty with a place for conscience and freedom, it could solve a central problem of politics. Most (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  48.  89
    Relying on Experts as We Reason Together.Henry S. Richardson - 2012 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 22 (2):91-110.
    In various contexts, it is thought to be important that we reason together. For instance, an attractive conception of democracy requires that citizens reach lawmaking decisions by reasoning with one another. Reasoning requires that reasoners survey the considerations that they take to be reasons, proceed by a coherent train of thought, and reach conclusions freely. De facto reliance on experts threatens the possibility of collective reasoning by making some reasons collectively unsurveyable, raising questions about the coherence of the resulting train (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  35
    Nussbaum: Love and Respect.Henry S. Richardson - 1998 - Metaphilosophy 29 (4):254-262.
    This article details how Martha Nussbaum has heightened the potential tension between love and respect, flagged by Kant, by strengthening what each requires. She elaborates the particularism and disruptiveness of love while insisting on a cosmopolitanism of respect. The article suggests that dealing with this tension will require developing a more detailed theory of institutional justice, one that can extend to the international arena.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. Feminist philosophy of science: history, contributions, and challenges.Sarah S. Richardson - 2010 - Synthese 177 (3):337-362.
    Feminist philosophy of science has led to improvements in the practices and products of scientific knowledge-making, and in this way it exemplifies socially relevant philosophy of science. It has also yielded important insights and original research questions for philosophy. Feminist scholarship on science thus presents a worthy thought-model for considering how we might build a more socially relevant philosophy of science—the question posed by the editors of this special issue. In this analysis of the history, contributions, and challenges faced by (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
1 — 50 / 944